pelicanweblogo2010

Mother Pelican
A Journal of Solidarity and Sustainability

Vol. 14, No. 9, September 2018
Luis T. Gutiťrrez, Editor
Home Page
Front Page

motherpelicanlogo2012


For the Love of Reason

Sheldon Richman

Originally published in
MCW News, 11 August 2018
under a Creative Commons License


09.18.Page12.Reason.jpg


Far be it from me to divide humankind in two, but were I so inclined, Iíd divide it into those who love reason and those who are indifferent if not outright hostile to it. Members of the first group adore the reasoning process and their own reasoning faculties.

The others find the process burdensome and discomforting, something that threatens long-held beliefs and intuitions. When I say the members of the first group adore their own reasoning faculties, I do not mean that they are arrogantly confident in their intelligence or immunity from error. Quite the contrary: a Spinozist love of reason contains within it humility, doubt, an awareness of oneís limits and fallibility, and recognition of the inherently social nature of reason (and language) and the growth of knowledge.

The thing to read in this regard is John Stuart Millís On Liberty, a paean to the free and competitive marketplace of ideas. Mill wished to establish that this marketplace was indispensable to learning or at least to approaching the truth. My favorite line, which admirably summarizes most of the little book, is this: ďHe who knows only his own side of the case, knows little of that.Ē

Taking that proposition to heart puts one in the right frame of mind to engage in argument. Itís tempting to approach an argument like a high-school debater: I have a proposition to defend, and, damn it, I intend to do just that. This need not imply a willingness to lie or to make dubious moves; rather, it merely implies an overinvestment in the proposition, a sense that, if I lose the argument, I have lost something big, something like a piece of myself. This is understandable. Beliefs form a worldview; a belief shaken is a worldview shaken, and thatís not easy to take. Losing could also mean being or feeling obligated to do things I would rather not do or stop doing things Iím fond of doing.

But, in my view, thatís a bad attitude. I try to think of argument the way I think of trade: both sides gain no matter how the interaction comes out. (Think of what John Stossel calls the ďdouble thank youĒ moment that occurs at the store checkout counter.) How can that be?

Millís sentence tells us. If you ďwinĒ the argument ó and you can do this even if the interlocutor doesnít seem convinced ó you will likely have learned more about your own position simply by hearing it criticized. Being required to answer counterarguments will prompt you to plumb the depths of the topic youíre exploring, and you are likely to think of things you might never have thought of otherwise. Thatís good! Youíll know your own position better because you know at least some arguments against it. Since you donít know whether other counterarguments exist, you can look forward to the next intellectual joust as an opportunity to find out.

On the other hand, if you ďloseĒ the argument, you still gain because you have shed an erroneous belief and are now closer to acquiring knowledge that you lacked before the argument. Thatís good too.

Itís win-win, just like trade.

Iím not saying the process is one of unmitigated joy. We human beings naturally become attached to our beliefs, intuitions, and conclusions. We can develop a proprietary interest in them. As a result, we are not eager to see them rendered worthless. The reasonable person is not one who never feels that attachment but rather one who puts the attachment aside for the sake of learning. Like an Aristotelian virtue, openness to intellectual challenge can become second nature as one strives to make a habit of it. Practice makes virtue, and discomfort fades.

Itís no coincidence that argument resembles trade: itís a form of trade, even if it doesnít always feel like one. The marketplace of ideas is like the marketplace of goods and services. (Of course, access to an idea can be a marketplace good.) In both cases, people assert propositions ó goods embody propositions ó and theyíll find out whether better alternatives are available.

In the commercial marketplace, sellers present their case that their goods at the asking price offer the best way for potential buyers to accomplish their objectives. Competing sellers make counterarguments. Prospective buyers weigh the arguments, looking for flaws. Thus the epistemological case for a free market in goods and services is identical to the case for a free market in ideas. We learn important things about how to flourish that we would likely otherwise not learn. (This was Ludwig von Misesís and F. A. Hayekís argument against central economic planning.)

Finally, the libertarian philosophy of full individual liberty ó which includes the right to justly acquired material objects ó embodies the love of reason as Iíve described it. The libertarian ethic ó the nonaggression principle or, as I prefer, obligation ó holds that, if you deal with others, you ought to deal with them through reason, not just for their sake but for your own. Persuasion is the opposite of force, though I acknowledge that someone peopleís discomfort with reason stems from their conflating the metaphorical compulsion of a good argument with the actual compulsion of a government command. The libertarian philosophy embraces Athens ó reason and persuasion ó over Jerusalem ó revelation and commandment.

I think this provides a case for the free society that is in a sense Cartesian. Descartes of course wrote that one can doubt everything except the existence of doubt and the doubter. (Iím not saying I agree with Descartes.) Applying something like this method to ethics and politics, we may say that, while one may reasonably doubt propositions about how society ought to be constituted, one cannot reasonably doubt the value of doubt and thus the freedom to doubt.

So stated, my proposition might win something broad assent, so Iíll push it further. If one should have the freedom to doubt ó call it the right to doubt ó then one should also have the right to express doubt. Expressing it is necessary to ascertain if it is reasonable. And if one has the right to express doubt, one has the right to acquire the physical means of maintaining oneís life and of expressing doubt. Iím using right to mean a valid claim to be free from aggressive force and to defend against such aggression, so naturally oneís exercise of this right cannot entail the use of aggressive of force against others, who also have the right. Needless to say, respect for such rights will generate a variety of humane institutions.

Any doubters out there?


ABOUT THE AUTHOR

Sheldon Richman keeps the blog Free Association and is chairman of the trustees of the Center for a Stateless Society. He is the executive editor of The Libertarian Institute and the author of the The Future of Freedom Foundation's award-winning books, Separating School & State: How to Liberate America's Families, Your Money or Your Life: Why We Must Abolish the Income Tax, and Tethered Citizens: Time to Repeal the Welfare State.


|Back to Title|

LINK TO THE CURRENT ISSUE          LINK TO THE HOME PAGE

"A mind all logic is like a knife all blade.
It makes the hand bleed that uses it."


Rabindranath Tagore (1861-1841)

GROUP COMMANDS AND WEBSITES

Write to the Editor
Send email to Subscribe
Send email to Unsubscribe
Link to the Google Groups Website
Link to the PelicanWeb Home Page

CREATIVE
COMMONS
LICENSE
Creative Commons License
ISSN 2165-9672

Page 12      

FREE SUBSCRIPTION

[groups_small]

Subscribe to the
Mother Pelican Journal
via the Solidarity-Sustainability Group

Enter your email address: